Schiller--Letters
on the Aesthetic Education of Man
We are impelled by two opposing forces:
1) the sensuous drive (Stofftrieb)--The sensuous drive
"proceeds from the physical existence of man."
It is characterized by change: "this drive demands
that there shall be change, that time shall have a
content."
This is the drive that keeps man tied to phenomenal existence:
"Man in this state is nothing but a unit of quantity, an
occupied moment of time--or rather, he is not at all, for his
personality is suspended as long as he is ruled by sensation,
and swept along by the flux of time."
2) the formal drive (Formtrieb)--The formal drive
"proceeds from the absolute existence of man."
This is the force of unity in the self. It is "that
drive which insists on affirming the personality," and its
quest is for "the abstract, eternal, and absolute."
This drive "gives laws--laws for every judgment, where
it is a question of knowledge, laws for every will, where it is
a question of action."
These drives are united and transcended in the play drive (Spieltrieb).
This drive is "directed towards annulling time within
time, reconciling becoming with absolute being and change with
identity."
*
According
to Schiller, the rise of civilization fragmented the
individual. At the time of the Greeks, sense and intellect
had not yet split into separate--and opposing--domains. With
the moderns, "the human species is projected in magnified
form into separate individuals--but as fragments." Schiller
blames this fragmentation on "the increase of empirical
knowledge, and the more exact modes of thought,
[which] made sharper divisions between the sciences
inevitable, and . . . necessitated a more rigorous separation
of ranks and occupations."
Schiller
postulates that we are impelled by two opposing forces: 1)
the sensuous drive (Stofftrieb); 2) the formal drive (Formtrieb).
The sensuous drive "proceeds from the physical
existence of man." Essentially it is characterized by
change: "this drive demands that there shall be change,
that time shall have a content." This is the drive that
keeps man tied to phenomenal existence: "Man in this state
is nothing but a unit of quantity, an occupied moment of
time--or rather, he is not at all, for his personality is
suspended as long as he is ruled by sensation, and swept along
by the flux of time."
The formal
drive "proceeds from the absolute existence of
man." This is the force of unity in the self. It is
"that drive which insists on affirming the
personality," and its quest is for "the abstract,
eternal, and absolute." This drive "gives
laws--laws for every judgement, where it is a question of
knowledge, laws for every will, where it is a question of
action."
These drives
are united and transcended in the play drive (Spieltrieb).
This drive is "directed towards annulling time within
time, reconciling becoming with absolute being and change with
identity."
Man is
only fully human when he plays, and he plays with beauty:
"the agreeable, the good, the perfect, with these man is
merely in earnest; but with beauty he plays." The aesthetic
state--as with Kant--is separate from issues of sensual pleasure
or intellectual morality. beauty "accomplishes no
particular purpose, neither intellectual nor moral." The
aesthetic does, however, possess great power: it heals--at
least temporarily--those who have lost their "humanity . .
. with every determinate condition [they] . . . enter" by
restoring their humanity--helping them transcend their
externally determined condition-- "through the life of the
aesthetic."
No "purely
aesthetic effect" is ever found, but a work of art can be
"a high approximation" of the "ideal of aesthetic
purity." The closer the various art forms come to this
ideal, the more they resemble one another in their effect on the
human psyche. In truly successful art, the contents--no
matter how noble--are not the point: the form is that
from which "true aesthetic freedom can be looked for."
Schiller takes a
nice swipe (200 years early) at late-20th-century critics who
judge the whole by parts; this is:
"evidence
of a lack of form in him who judges [the art object]. If he is .
. . used to apprehending either exclusively with the intellect
or exclusively with the senses, he will, even in the case of the
most successfully realized whole, attend only to the parts, and
in the presence of the most beauteous form respond only to the
matter. Receptive only to the raw material, he has first to
destroy the aesthetic organization of a work before he can take
pleasure in it, and laboriously scratch away until he has
uncovered all those individual details which the master, with
infinite skill, had caused to disappear in the harmony of the
whole. The interest he takes in it is quite simply either a
moral or a material interest; but what precisely it ought to
be, namely aesthetic, that it certainly is not."
Aesthetic
contemplation in the realm of the play-drive prepares man to
"assert his independence in the face of nature as
phenomenon." This echoes the effect of the Kantian
dynamic sublime which helps us to become "conscious that we
are superior to nature." |